The American Psychiatric Association (APA) has updated its Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including with new information specifically addressed to individuals in the European Economic Area. As described in the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, this website utilizes cookies, including for the purpose of offering an optimal online experience and services tailored to your preferences.

Please read the entire Privacy Policy and Terms of Use. By closing this message, browsing this website, continuing the navigation, or otherwise continuing to use the APA's websites, you confirm that you understand and accept the terms of the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including the utilization of cookies.

×
Special ArticleFull Access

Déjà Vu: Possible Parahippocampal Mechanisms

Published Online:https://doi.org/10.1176/jnp.14.1.6

Abstract

Déjà vu experiences are common in normal subjects. In addition, they are established symptoms of temporal lobe seizures. The author argues that the phenomenon is the result of faulty and isolated activity of a recognition memory system that consists of the parahippocampal gyrus and its neocortical connections. This memory system is responsible for judgments of familiarity. The result is that a momentary perceived scene is given the characteristics of familiarity that normally accompany a conscious recollection. The normal functioning of other brain structures involved in memory retrieval—the prefrontal cortex and the hippocampus proper—leads to the perplexing phenomenological quality of déjà vu. The hypothesis accounts for many characteristics of déjà vu in healthy subjects and is well fitting with experimental findings in patients with epilepsy.

Most people at some times experience déjà vu (DV). In a questionnaire study about paroxysmal psychic phenomena in a student population,1 only 10% of the subjects denied that they ever had experienced DV. In the same study, 56% of participants reported that they had had DV experiences in the preceding month. Although DV experiences have no behavioral counterpart, most people seem to agree on their phenomenological characteristics, and the ubiquity of the phenomenon is reflected in numerous descriptions in poetry and fiction.2 In addition, the DV experience has long been known as a seizure manifestation,3 and it is an established symptom—usually in association with other symptoms—of partial seizures of temporal lobe origin.4

The issue of DV has most often been treated at a psychodynamic level,5,6 and only few attempts have been made to explain DV at the level of brain–behavior relationship. One strictly somatic hypothesis was proposed by Efron,7 who argued that material pertinent to time perception is received by the nondominant hemisphere and transferred to the hemisphere dominant for language. Functional or anatomical nondominant temporal lobe damage may delay transfer of information and might cause the left dominant hemisphere to receive the information twice, once directly and once delayed via the right hemisphere. Newly perceived material thus is rendered familiar by virtue of the near-simultaneous double presentation. Although ingenious, this idea does not seem to have received much independent support. Moreover, it is not clear why this mechanism should not lead to a feeling of having experienced a situation just before, and not somewhere in an undefined past.

Using holography as an analogy for memory processes, Sno and Linszen5 have emphasized that DV experiences should not be thought of as pure memory or pure perceptive disturbances, but as a result of a disturbed interaction between memory and perception processes.

The results of electrophysiological studies in patients with epilepsy, together with recent advances in our knowledge about the functional architecture of memory processes, give us the opportunity to set up a more specific hypothesis about the cognitive mechanism of DV.

THE PHENOMENON TO BE EXPLAINED

DV experiences are subjectively inappropriate impressions of familiarity of the present with an undefined past.8 They are not necessarily connected with significant events or deep emotion. No differences between the sexes have been found, but DV seems to be more frequent in young subjects,2 and it can be triggered by drowsiness or fatigue.9

DV experiences are not vague feelings; reports typically include the term “exactly” or “to every last detail.”2 We even use the idiom “it's like a déjà vu” for a real remembrance, when we want to express its special vividness. The scene or episode appears to be not only exactly the same as what happened before, but also to be perceived in the same manner, from the same point of view and in the same state of mind, as when seemingly originally encountered. DV experiences have been described as photographic copies of an alleged experience in the past.5 On the other hand, the immediate feeling of inappropriateness of the experience sharply distinguishes the phenomenon from hallucinations and from “false memories.”10

Typically no context, and especially no temporal context, can be retrieved.11 It is this characteristic feature of DV experiences that has led many laypersons to interpret them as reminiscences from a former life.12

From exploration of DV as a seizure manifestation in temporal lobe epilepsy and after electrical brain stimulation, it is known that temporal lobe structures are heavily involved in DV.1316 Whereas earlier studies had emphasized the role of neocortical temporal stimulation for the generation of experimental phenomena,13 later workers have found a preponderance of mesiotemporal limbic structures.14,17 Furthermore, it has been suggested that DV experiences are reported only when both mesiotemporal and neocortical temporal areas are involved.16

In epilepsy research, however, the phenomenon of DV is usually discussed in a broader context—termed by Jackson “dreamy state”3—that does not include DV alone, but scenic,16 auditory, and visual hallucinations13 as well. Unlike hallucinations, typical DV as experienced by normal subjects is not accompanied by impaired reality testing. So the specific substrate for DV in its narrower sense, which has also been called “forme légère” or “minor form,”18 has not been focused on.

THE ARCHITECTURE OF MEMORY RETRIEVAL

The importance of the mesial temporal lobe, and especially the hippocampus, for episodic memory processes has become firmly established, but there is agreement that the mesiotemporal memory system is not important for all types of memory.19 Mesiotemporal memory structures do not seem to have an important role in the learning of skills,20 in unconscious priming effects,21 or in assessing knowledge that is not bound to a specific situation (semantic memory).22,23 However, the mesiotemporal memory system is especially important when encoding or retrieval concerns autobiographical or episodic information.

The mesiotemporal memory system is not homogeneous. Not only the hippocampus proper, but also the entorhinal cortex and the neighboring perirhinal and parahippocampal cortices are important for memory processes. Moreover, the different structures seem to be important for different aspects or even subtypes of episodic memory. The perirhinal cortex receives strong projections from visual areas important for object recognition24 and might therefore be highly important for visual memory for objects. The parahippocampal cortex gets strong input from regions of the parietal cortex that are important for visuospatial processing,25 and it has been demonstrated in animal studies that the parahippocampal gyrus is involved in spatial aspects of memory.19 In humans as well, lesion studies in neurological patients26,27 and functional imaging studies28 have shown that the parahippocampal gyrus is especially relevant for memory for the location of objects.

Specialization among the structures might not be restricted to the type of material to be encoded; it could reflect a more basic differentiation between different memory systems. In animal studies it has been shown that although learning and retrieval can readily be accomplished by the parahippocampal cortex alone, the hippocampus proper is needed to make these associations flexible, hence to make them applicable under changing conditions and to combine information acquired under different learning situations.29 It seems that while the hippocampus might be needed for a deliberative remembrance of previous episodes, parahippocampal activation, as Gabrieli and colleagues have noted, “could reflect other memory processes that distinguish between familiar and unfamiliar stimuli.”30

This view has been expressed more explicitly by Aggleton and Brown,31 who differentiated between two memory systems partly situated in the mesial temporal lobe. The first, including the hippocampus, enables recall and conscious recollection of contextual elements. The second, which includes the parahippocampal cortex, is important for familiarity judgments or the “feeling of knowing.” These authors also emphasize the distinction between viewer-independent allocentric and viewer-dependent egocentric spatial processing, with only the former being dependent on an intact hippocampus. Therefore, the parahippocampal recognition system might be sufficient for memorizing a specific view of a scene, but only by virtue of the hippocampus can one use this information for constructing and remembering a representation of a spatial layout as it is necessary for spatial orientation and navigation.32 Simplistically, one could say that the representation of a place in parahippocampal terms is like a photograph of the scene, whereas for the hippocampus it is like a map. DV is much more like looking at a photograph than it is like looking at a map.

The mesial temporal lobe and interconnected diencephalic counterparts31 are not the only structures involved in memory retrieval. During retrieval tasks in functional imaging studies, prefrontal areas are even more consistently activated.33 While it has been suggested that the mesiotemporal structures are involved in actual recollection, prefrontal activation reflects strategic memory search34 and the reconstruction of the general context of an event.10 Furthermore, the frontal networks are especially important for remembering the time when an event took place and the temporal order among events.35,36

THE HYPOTHESIS

I argue that DV is the phenomenological result of a false activation of connections between mesiotemporal memory structures and neocortical areas directly involved in the perception of the environment. This false activation results in wrongly labeling a momentary perceived scene as familiar. I argue further that in DV this activation remains isolated. According to the presented hypothesis, DV experiences reflect an inflexible parahippocampal recognition memory system, responsible for feelings of familiarity,37 working in isolation while the more flexible hippocampal recall system is not involved. This does not imply that the hippocampus does not work properly. To the contrary: a normally working hippocampus together with a normally functioning prefrontal system is a prerequisite to recognize the illusionary character of a DV experience and to remember it afterwards.

DV experiences reflect a memory system that is highly involved in spatial processing in an egocentric sense—and not in the way the hippocampus is needed for building up and holding an allocentric representation of space important for navigation.32 During a DV experience one seems to recognize every single detail of a scene, as if comparing it to a photograph, and nevertheless one has no idea how it looks behind one's back or around the next corner. This stands in contrast to normal remembrances: when one comes to a place one has not been for a long time, everything seems to look a little bit different than remembered (smaller if one was last there as a child), and one is not entirely sure which details have changed since and which not. On the other hand, however, one at least vaguely remembers which way one would go to other formerly known places in the surroundings, and what kind of turn the road makes behind one's back.

EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE

Although electrophysiological data have convincingly demonstrated the contribution of mesiotemporal structures in epileptic DV,14,16,38 clinical and methodological considerations have limited the systematic efforts to study the separate contributions of the different structures. Nevertheless, data from the existing studies are in agreement with the hypothesis. In one study,16 different symptoms were included under the label “vivid recollection” or “dreamy states,” and seizures were recorded from a wide area within the mesial and the neocortical temporal lobe. Nevertheless, in 4 of the 6 patients who reported DV, ictal activity was recorded in the parahippocampal gyrus, whereas this was the case in only 2 of the 10 patients with other symptoms such as hallucinations or isolated feelings of strangeness.

In a study of patients with strictly defined, spontaneously occurring epileptic DV experiences,38 mesiotemporal seizure onset was found in all cases. Subdural strip electrodes were used that do not directly monitor the hippocampus, but rather the parahippocampal gyrus. The consistent finding of epileptiform activity is therefore compatible with the view that it was the relevant structure—the parahippocampal gyrus—that was monitored. As no stereotactic implanted electrodes were used, however, this study could not clarify the role of the hippocampus proper.

Experimental experiences can be evoked by stimulation not only of medial temporal structures, but also of temporal neocortex.13,16 According to the hypothesis, neocortical areas that are directly connected to the parahippocampal gyrus should be preferentially involved in DV. Indeed, DV experiences have been documented after stimulation of the directly connected superior temporal gyrus,14 and not after stimulation of the inferior and middle temporal gyri,13 areas that are connected with the hippocampus via the perirhinal cortex.24 In patients with mesiotemporal epilepsy who experienced DV as part of their seizures, parietal lobe hypometabolism has been demonstrated.39 Because of their widespread brain damage, the sample in that study might not be representative. Nevertheless, the results were clear enough to allow the authors to argue that DV might stem from a mismatch between memory and perceptive processes. I certainly agree, but the data seem to allow a more specific hypothesis. Not all brain areas relevant for memory and perception were activated, only parietal ones. In view of the substantial anatomical projection from area 7 of the parietal cortex to the parahippocampal cortex,19,25 this fits well with the hypothesis proposed here.

Even if one accepts the suggested mechanism and the similarity between DV as an ictal phenomenon and DV in normal subjects, the question remains open, why DV happens at all in normal subjects. Although DV might be an ictal phenomenon in normal individuals as it is in patients with epilepsy, the potential of drowsiness to elicit DV points to a more plausible explanation. Sleep is not accompanied by a global decrease of brain activity but by a selective change in the pattern of activity.40 The role of sleep for consolidation of memory traces has been emphasized,41 and it has been argued that this might be achieved by a more intensive functional connectivity between mesiotemporal and neocortical structures during sleep. This might be accompanied by weakened functional interconnections within association cortex. While enabling the reorganization of connectivity in favor of memory consolidation, as a by-product these alterations would lead to a higher susceptibility to DV experiences. In this context it might be interesting that DV experiences often have been compared with dreams.42 So, DV experiences in normal individuals might—like dreams—be a by-product of a mechanism that is responsible for memory consolidation.

Despite the subjective and fleeting character of the phenomenon, the hypothesis is testable. First, it is based on the prevailing interpretation of the available data on the role of mesial temporal structures and neocortex for memory retrieval, which is far from settled. Every substantial change in our knowledge about the episodic memory system will thus either support or undermine the hypothesis to the extent that new experimental data confirm or disconfirm the underlying theories. More directly, electrophysiological studies using stereotactic implanted electrodes in patients with epilepsy could clarify the roles of the different parts of the mesiotemporal system in generating epileptic DV. Finally, a way to test the hypothesis would be to capture a DV event during H215O PET, as was done in migraine headache,43 or during performance of another suitable functional imaging procedure. However, one would have to be very lucky to have DV occur by chance under these conditions, especially in normal subjects.

POSTSCRIPT

Cognitive neurosciences have demonstrated that cognitive processes can be dissociated, that they often work in parallel,44 and that they do not converge on a “central observer.”45 Normally all of these processes work together in a way that gives us the impression of a unitary process. Only when something goes wrong does the distinctness of these processes become observable. Such a situation can be found in neurological disorders and is the starting point for cognitive neuropsychology. In healthy subjects as well, sometimes lapses allow glimpses into the cognitive machinery working in the background. Well-known examples are optical illusions.46 DV experiences give us the rare opportunity of an immediate glance at the isolated performance of one of our systems relevant for remembering. Through an explanation of DV at a neuropsychological level, it may become possible to reconcile theoretical knowledge about the dissociations within the memory system with our genuine experience of an integral and unitary memory of the past.

Received November 17, 2000; revised February 10, 2001; accepted February 21, 2001. From Ludwig Boltzmann Institute for Epilepsy and Neuromuscular Disorders, Rosenhügel Neurological Hospital, Vienna, Austria. Address correspondence to Dr. Spatt, II. Neurologische Abteilung, Neurologisches Krankenhaus Rosenhügel, Riedelgasse 5, 1130 Vienna, Austria. E-mail:
References

1 Ardila A, Niño CR, Pulido E, et al: Episodic psychic symptoms in the general population. Epilepsia 1993; 34:133-140Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

2 Sno HN, Linszen DH, de Jonghe F: Art imitates life: déjà vu experiences in prose and poetry. Br J Psychiatry 1992; 160:511-518Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

3 Jackson JH, Colman WS: Case of epilepsy with tasting movements and “dreamy state”: very small patch of softening in the left uncinate gyrus. Brain 1898; 21:580-590CrossrefGoogle Scholar

4 Gil-Nagel A, Risinger MW: Ictal semiology in hippocampal versus extrahippocampal temporal lobe epilepsy. Brain 1997; 120:183-192Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

5 Sno HN, Linszen DH: The déjà experience: remembrance of things past? Am J Psychiatry 1990; 147:1587-1595Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

6 Berrios GE: Déjà vu in France during the 19th century: a conceptual history. Compr Psychiatry 1995; 36:123-129Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

7 Efron R: Temporal perception, aphasia and déjà vu. Brain 1963; 86:403-424Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

8 Neppe VM: The concept of déjà vu. Parapsychology Journal of South Africa 1983; 4:1-10Google Scholar

9 Freud S: Fausse reconnaissance (déjà raqconté) in psychoanalytic treatment, in Collected Papers. London, Hogarth, 1933, pp 334-341Google Scholar

10 Schacter DL: Illusory memories: a cognitive neuroscience analysis. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1996; 93:13527-13533Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

11 Sno HN, Schalken HFA, de Jonghe F, et al: The inventory for déjà vu experiences assessment: development, utility, reliability, and validity. J Nerv Ment Dis 1994; 182:27-33Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

12 Scott W: The Journal of Sir Walter Scott. Edinburgh, D. Douglas, 1890, p 124Google Scholar

13 Penfield W, Perot P: The brain's record of auditory and visual experience: a final summary and discussion. Brain 1963; 86:595-696Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

14 Gloor P: Experimental phenomena of temporal lobe epilepsy: facts and hypotheses. Brain 1990; 113:1673-1694Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

15 Halgren E, Chauvel P: Experimental phenomena evoked by human brain electrical stimulation. Adv Neurol 1992; 65:87-104Google Scholar

16 Bancaud J, Brunet-Bourgin F, Chauvel P, et al: Anatomical origin of déjà vu and vivid “memories” in human temporal lobe epilepsy. Brain 1994; 117:71-90Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

17 Gloor P, Olivier A, Quesney LF, et al: The role of the limbic system in experimental phenomena of temporal lobe epilepsy. Ann Neurol 1982; 12:129-144Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

18 Arnaud FL: Un cas d'illusion de fausse mémoire. Ann Med Psychol 1896; 3:455-471Google Scholar

19 Squire LR, Zola SM: Structure and function of declarative and nondeclarative memory systems. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1996; 93:13515-13522Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

20 Cohen NJ, Squire LR: Preserved learning and retention of pattern-analyzing skill in amnesia: dissociation of knowing how and knowing that. Science 1980; 240:207-210CrossrefGoogle Scholar

21 Tulving E, Schacter DL: Priming and human memory systems. Science 1990; 247:301-306Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

22 Patterson K, Hodges JR: Disorders of semantic memory, in Handbook of Memory Disorders, 1st edition, edited by Baddeley AD, Wilson BA, Watts FN. New York, Wiley, 1995, pp 176-186Google Scholar

23 Tranel D, Damasio H, Damasio AR: A neural basis for the retrieval of conceptual knowledge. Neuropsychologia 1997; 35:1319-1327Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

24 Webster MJ, Ungerleider LG, Bachevalier J: Connections of inferior temporal areas TE and TEO with medial temporal-lobe structures in infant and adult monkeys. J Neurosci 1991; 11:1095-1116Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

25 Suzuki WA, Amarel DG: Perirhinal and parahippocampal cortices of the macaque monkey: cortical afferents. J Comp Neurol 1994; 3:497-533CrossrefGoogle Scholar

26 Köhler S, Black SE, Sinden M, et al: Memory impairments associated with hippocampal versus parahippocampal-gyrus atrophy: an MR volumetry study in Alzheimer's disease. Neuropsychologia 1998; 36:901-914Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

27 Bohbot VD, Kalina M, Stepankova K, et al: Spatial memory deficits in patients with lesions to the right hippocampus and to the right parahippocampal cortex. Neuropsychologia 1998; 36:1217-1238Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

28 Aguirre GK, Zarahn E, D'Esposito M: Neural components of topographical representation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1998; 95:839-846Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

29 Eichenbaum H, Otto T, Cohen NJ: Two functional components of the hippocampal memory system. Behav Brain Sci 1994; 17:449-518CrossrefGoogle Scholar

30 Gabrieli JDE, Brewer JB, Desmond JE, et al: Separate neural basis of two fundamental memory processes in the human medial temporal lobe. Science 1997; 276:264-265Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

31 Aggleton JP, Brown MW: Episodic memory, amnesia, and the hippocampal-anterior thalamic axis. Behav Brain Sci 1999; 22:425-489Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

32 O'Keefe J, Nadel L: The Hippocampus as a Cognitive Map. Oxford, UK, Oxford University Press, 1978Google Scholar

33 Buckner RL, Kelley WM, Petersen SE: Frontal cortex contributes to human memory formation. Nat Neurosci 1999; 2:311-314Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

34 Schacter DL, Alpert NM, Savage CR, et al: Conscious recollection and the human hippocampal formation: evidence from positron emission tomography. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1996; 93:321-325Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

35 Sagar HJ, Gabrieli JDE, Sullivan EV, et al: Recency and frequency discrimination in the amnestic patient H.M. Brain 1990; 113:581-602Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

36 Yasuno F, Hirata M, Takimoto H, et al: Retrograde temporal order amnesia resulting from damage to the fornix. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry 1999; 67:102-105Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

37 Milner PM: A cell assembly theory of hippocampal amnesia. Neuropsychologia 1989; 27:23-30Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

38 Weinand ME, Hermann BP, Wyler AR, et al: Long-term subdural strip electrographic monitoring of ictal déjà vu. Epilepsia 1994; 35:1054-1059Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

39 Adachi N, Koutroumanidis M, Elwes RDC, et al: Interictal 18FDG PET findings in temporal lobe epilepsy with déjà vu. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci 1999; 11:380-386LinkGoogle Scholar

40 Braun AR, Balkin TJ, Wesensten NJ, et al: Regional cerebral blood flow throughout the sleep-wake cycle: an H215O PET study. Brain 1997; 120:1173-1197Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

41 Wilson MA, McNaughton BL: Reactivation of hippocampal ensemble memories during sleep. Science 1994; 265:676-679Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

42 Epstein AW, Freeman NR: Case report: the uncinate focus and dreaming. Epilepsia 1981; 22:603-605Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

43 Woods RP, Iacoboni M, Mazziotta JC: Brief report: bilateral spreading cerebral hypoperfusion during spontaneous migraine headache. N Engl J Med 1994; 331:1689-1692Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

44 Mesulam MM: From sensation to cognition. Brain 1998; 121:1013-1052Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

45 Dennett DC: Consciousness Explained. Boston, Little, Brown, 1991Google Scholar

46 Gregory RL: Eye and Brain. Oxford, UK, Oxford University Press, 1998Google Scholar